Wednesday, August 8, 2012

643 Words About Inferentialism, Disquotationalism, the Tonk Problem and the Liar Paradox

A popular view about the semantic function of the truth predicate is that "truth is disquotation." A classic explanation of this comes from Quine, who claims in a famous passage in "Philosophy of Logic" that the semantic effect of appending "is true" to a quoted sentence is to cancel out the quotation marks. Thus, when we say "'Snow is white' is true", we're not talking about the sentence and attributing some property to it--e.g. correspondence or coherence or whatever. Instead, we're talking about snow and attributing whiteness to it. (Of course, in that example, asserting that snow is white in this indirect way is just redundant, but there are plenty of familiar contexts--e.g. "blind endorsements" like Jack saying "everything Jill just said is true" when he can't necessarily remember every detail of what she said--in which having the truth predicate in our language does allow us to say things we couldn't say without it.)

A lot of people who call themselves disquotationalists don't spell out exactly what they mean by 'disquotationalism', preferring to leave it at a rough intuitive level, and I'm pretty sure quite a few pretty much what Quine did, but a lot of others (like, e.g. JC Beall) make it clear that they mean something slightly different. They start with something like inferentialism about logical connectives--the view that the meaning of the connectives is defined by the logical rules governing them--and apply this to the truth predicate, such that the rules allowing one to derive "'P' is true" from "P" and vice versa are taken to somehow "define" the term "true."

We can think of the first version as "meaning-equivalence disquotationalism" and the second version as "inferentialist disquotationalism." I argued in my dissertation that meaning-equivalence disquotationism gives us a good, principled non-ad-hoc reason to think that sentences like "This sentence is true" and, crucially, its paradoxical cousin "This sentence is not true" are meaningless. After all, if "is true" doesn't add any semantic content to a sentence--and a sentence like "this sentence is true" has nowhere else to gets its content--it ends up just not having any.

But what about inferentialist disquotationalism?

A familiar objection to inferentialism in general is the "tonk problem." What if I introduce a connective called "tonk" with the same introduction rules as disjuncton--so, "P tonk Q" follows from "P"--and the same elimination rules as conjunction, such that "Q" follows from "P tonk Q"?

This problem has been around forever, and while some people--and I'm one of them--take it to render inferentialism painfully implausible, clearly, lots of inferentialists are willing to live with it. "Living with it" clearly means imposing some sort of restrictions on which sorts of rules can create meanings. The phrase "well-defined" is often muttered at this juncture.

Of course, tonk is entirely well-defined--it simply combines the well-defined introduction rules of disjunction with the well-defined elimination rules of conjunction--unless part of what you mean by well-defined is something like "consistent" or "non-trivial" or some other way of saying "fits with our basic logical assumptions."

....which is fine. (Again, not my preferred way of going about things--especially since making those sorts of moves makes it impossible to have a non-question-begging argument with someone who questions those basic logical assumptions--but, for present purposes, let's say that it's fine.) But, if we can just see the logical implications of allowing some connective and declare it logically impossible that it's meaningful, why can't we do the same thing with sentences? If inferentialism works, it's because we can impose a logical-possibility constraint on meaningfulness, and if we can do that, it looks to me like we have an even quicker way of getting to the meaninglessness conclusion about paradoxical sentences than we did with meaning-equivalence disquotationalism.

3 comments:

Colin said...

Hey Ben, glad to see you back at the blog. I agree with your concluding remarks but I would want to spell the point out thusly: if the only reason for being an inferentialist were to justify the thesis that paradoxical sentences are meaningless, then no one needs to be an inferentialist because there are more direct arguments for the same conclusion. But of course most people who are inferentialists are not interested in the paradoxes at all. Rather, they think inferentialist is simply the truth about how certain expressions get their meaning. Stephen Read, for example, has a very different attitude toward tonk than many people. While he agrees that tonk is meaningless he think this is because it violates the minimal conditions on meaning-conferring rules and not because it leads to inconsistency. In fact, Read says that an even more directly paradoxical connective 'bullet' is perfectly meaningful. I've been puzzling over the connection between consistency and meaning quite a lot myself recently. I'd be interested to hear your further thoughts on the matter.

Ben said...

Just saw this. What's Read's objection to Tonk?

Colin said...

You'll be unsurprised to hear that tonk is disharmonious. For Read and a few others, harmony of intro and elim rules is a necessary condition on meaningfulness. Just now, in writing this, it occurs to me that of course one could happily go along with the harmony constraint but see this as a *merely* necessary but insufficient condition for meaningfulness. This view would also agree that tonk is a meaningless connective, but it would be an open question what to say about other 'funny' cases like Read's bullet (which I think actually originated with Shroeder-Heister but I'm not sure). On a separate point, of course one can and should be skeptical about substantive inferentialist proposals such as harmony constraints. Nonetheless, Read and others like him show that one can have independent motives for inferentialism on which consistency and meaningfulness come apart, which was all that I wanted to illustrate.